首页 > 题库 > 考研考博 > 考博英语 > 南开大学 > 单选题

Anyone who trains animals recognizes that human and animal perceptual capacities are different. For most humans, seeing is believing, although we do occasionally brood about whether we can believe our eyes. The other senses are largely ancillary; most of us do not know how we might go about either doubting or believing our noses. But for dogs, scenting is believing. A dog’s nose is to ours as the wrinkled surface of our complex brain is to the surface of an egg. A dog who did comparative psychology might easily worry about our consciousness or lack thereof, just as we worry about the consciousness of a squid.
We who take sight for granted can draw pictures of scent, but we have no language for doing it the other way about, no way to represent something visually familiar by means of actual scent. Most humans cannot know, with their limited noses, what they can imagine about being deaf, blind, mute, or paralyzed. The sighted can, for example, speak of a blind person as “in the darkness,” but there is no corollary expression for what it is that we are in relationship to scent. If we tried to coin words, we might come up with something like “scent-blind.” But what would it mean? It couldn’t have the sort of meaning that “color-blind” and “tone-deaf” do, because most of us have experienced what “tone” and “color” mean in those expressions, but we don’t know what “scent” means in the expression “scent-blind.” Scent for many of us can be only a theoretical, technical expression that we use because our grammar requires that we have a noun to go in the sentences we are prompted to utter about animals, tracking. We don’t have a sense of scent. What we do have is a sense of smell—for Thanksgiving dinner and skunks and a number of things we call chemicals.
So if Fido and I are sitting on the terrace, admiring the view, we inhabit worlds with radically different principles of phenomenology. Say that the wind is to our backs. Our world lies all before us, within a 180 degree angle. The dog’s—well, we don’t know, do we?
He sees roughly the same things that I see but he believes the scents of the garden behind us. He marks the path of the black-and white cat as she moves among the roses in search of the bits of chicken sandwich I let fall as I walked from the house to our picnic spot. I can show that Fido is alert to the kitty, but not how, for my picture-making modes of thought too easily supply falsifyingly literal representations of the cat and the garden and their modes of being hidden from or revealed to me.


1.The phrase “The other senses are largely ancillary” (Paragraph 1) is used by the author to suggest that( ).

2.The example in the last paragraph suggests that “principles of phenomenology” mentioned in Paragraph 3 can best be defined as( ).

3.The missing phrase in the incomplete sentence “The dog’s—well, we don’t know, do we?” refers to ( ) .

4.The example in the last paragraph is used to illustrate how( ).

问题1选项
A.only those events experienced directly can be appreciated by the senses
B.for many human beings the sense of sight is the primary means of knowing about the world
C.smell is in many respects a more powerful sense than sight
D.people rely on at least one of their other senses in order to confirm with what they see
问题2选项
A.rules one uses to determine the philosophical truth about a certain thing
B.behaviors caused by certain kinds of perception
C.ways and means of knowing about something
D.effect of single individual’s perception on what others believe
问题3选项
A.color blindness
B.perception of the world
C.concern for our perception
D.depth perception
问题4选项
A.a dog’s perception differs from a human’s
B.people fear nature but animals are part of it
C.a dog’s ways of seeing are superior to a cat’s
D.phenomenology is universal and constant
参考答案: 查看答案 查看解析 下载APP畅快刷题

相关知识点试题

相关试卷